Sunday, 30 October 2022

The Roots of War


First published in 1966, when the world situation was different -- but not that different -- to today, Ayn Rand argues in this essay that if nuclear weapons have made war too horrible to contemplate, and they have, then there is a horrible ideology that we can no longer afford to support ...

The Roots of War

by Ayn Rand

Reprinted by permission; originally published in the June 1966 issue of The Objectivist. Copyright 1966 by The Objectivist, Inc. Reprinted from the Foundation for Economic Education.

It is said that nuclear weapons have made wars too horrible to contemplate. Yet every nation on earth feels, in helpless terror, that such a war might come.

The overwhelming majority of mankind — the people who die on the battlefields or starve and per­ish among the ruins — do not want war. They never wanted it. Yet wars have kept erupting through­out the centuries, like a long trail of blood underscoring mankind’s history.

Men are afraid that war might come because they know, con­sciously or subconsciously, that they have never rejected the doc­trine which causes wars, which has caused the wars of the past and can do it again — the doctrine that it is right or practical or nec­essary for men to achieve their goals by means of physical force (by initiating the use of force against other men) and that some sort of "good" can justify it. It is the doctrine that force is a proper or unavoidable part of human existence and human societies.

Observe one of the ugliest char­acteristics of today’s world: the mixture of frantic war prepara­tions with hysterical peace prop­aganda, and the fact that both come from the same source — from the same political philosophy. The bankrupt, yet still dominant, po­litical philosophy of our age is statism.


Observe the nature of today’s alleged peace movements. Profes­sing love and concern for the sur­vival of mankind, they keep screaming that the nuclear-weap­ons race should be stopped, that armed force should be abolished as a means of settling disputes among nations, and that war should be outlawed in the name of humanity. Yet these same peace movements do not oppose dictator­ships; the political views of their members range through all shades of the statist spectrum, from welfare statism to socialism to fascism to communism. This means that they are opposed to the use of coercion by one nation against another, but not by the government of a nation against its own citizens; it means that they are opposed to the use of force against armed adversaries, but not against the disarmed.

Consider the plunder, the de­struction, the starvation, the bru­tality, the slave-labor camps, the torture chambers, the wholesale slaughter perpetrated by dictator­ships. Yet this is what today’s alleged peace-lovers are willing to advocate or tolerate—in the name of love for humanity.

It is obvious that the ideological root of statism (or collectivism) is the tribal premise of primordial savages who, unable to conceive of individual rights, believed that the tribe is a supreme, omnipotent ruler, that it owns the lives of its members and may sacrifice them whenever it pleases to whatever it deems to be its own "good." Un­able to conceive of any social prin­ciples, save the rule of brute force, they believed that the tribe’s wishes are limited only by its physical power and that other tribes are its natural prey, to be conquered, looted, enslaved or an­nihilated. The history of all primi­tive peoples in a succession of trib­al wars and intertribal slaughter. That this savage ideology now rules nations armed with nuclear weapons, should give pause to any­one concerned with mankind’s sur­vival.

Statism is a system of institu­tionalised violence and perpetual civil war. It leaves men no choice but to fight to seize political pow­er — to rob or be robbed, to kill or be killed. When brute force is the only criterion of social conduct, and unresisting surrender to de­struction is the only alternative, even the lowest of men, even an animal — even a cornered rat —will fight. There can be no peace within an enslaved nation.

The bloodiest conflicts of his­tory were not wars between na­tions, but civil wars between men of the same nation, who could find no peaceful recourse to law, prin­ciple or justice. Observe that the history of all absolute states is punctuated by bloody uprisings—by violent eruptions of blind des­pair, without ideology, program or goals—which were usually put down by ruthless extermination.

In a full dictatorship, statism’s chronic "cold" civil war takes the form of bloody purges, when one gang deposes another — as in Nazi Germany or Soviet Russia. In a mixed economy, it takes the form of pressure-group warfare, each group fighting for legislation to extort its own advantages by force from all other groups.

The degree of statism in a country’s political system, is the degree to which it breaks up the country into rival gangs and sets men against one another. When individual rights are abrogated, there is no way to determine who is entitled to what; there is no way to determine the justice of anyone’s claims, desires or inter­ests. The criterion, therefore, re­verts to the tribal concept of: one’s wishes are limited only by the power of one’s gang. In order to survive under such a system, men have no choice but to fear, hate and destroy one another; it is a system of underground plot­ting, of secret conspiracies, of deals, favors, betrayals and sud­den, bloody coups.

It is not a system conducive to brotherhood, security, cooperation and peace.

Statism — in fact and in prin­ciple — is nothing more than gang rule. A dictatorship is a gang de­voted to looting the effort of the productive citizens of its own country. When a statist ruler ex­hausts his own country’s economy, he attacks his neighbors. It is his only means of postponing internal collapse and prolonging his rule. A country that violates the rights of its own citizens, will not re­spect the rights of its neighbors. Those who do not recognize indi­vidual rights, will not recognize the rights of nations: a nation is only a number of individuals.


Statism needs war; a free coun­try does not. Statism survives by looting; a free country survives by production.

Observe that the major wars of history were started by the more controlled economies of the time against the freer ones. For in­stance, World War I was started by monarchist Germany and Czar­ist Russia, who dragged in their freer allies. World War II was started by the alliance of Nazi Germany with Soviet Russia and their joint attack on Poland.

Observe that in World War II, both Germany and Russia seized and dismantled entire factories in conquered countries, to ship them home—while the freest of the mixed economies, the semi-capitalistic United States, sent billions worth of lend-lease equip­ment, including entire factories, to its allies. [For a detailed, doc­umented account of the full extent of Russia’s looting, see East Minus West = Zero by Werner Keller, New York: G. P. Putnam’s Sons, 1962.]

Germany and Russia needed war; the United States did not and gained nothing. (In fact, the United States lost, economically, even though it won the war: it was left with an enormous na­tional debt, augmented by the gro­tesquely futile policy of supporting former allies and enemies to this day.) Yet it is capitalism that to­day’s peace-lovers oppose and stat­ism that they advocate — in the name of peace.

Laissez-faire capitalism is the only social system based on the recognition of individual rights and, therefore, the only system that bans force from social rela­tionships. By the nature of its basic principles and interests, it is the only system fundamentally op­posed to war.

Men who are free to produce, have no incentive to loot; they have nothing to gain from war and a great deal to lose. Ideologi­cally, the principle of individual rights does not permit a man to seek his own livelihood at the point of a gun, inside or outside his country. Economically, wars cost money; in a free economy, where wealth is privately owned, the costs of war come out of the income of private citizens — there is no overblown public treasury to hide that fact — and a citizen can­not hope to recoup his own finan­cial losses (such as taxes or busi­ness dislocations or property de­struction) by winning the war. Thus his own economic interests are on the side of peace.

In a statist economy, where wealth is "publicly owned," a citi­zen has no economic interests to protect by preserving peace — he is only a drop in the common buck­et — while war gives him the (fal­lacious) hope of larger handouts from his masters. Ideologically, he is trained to regard men as sacrificial animals; he is one him­self; he can have no concept of why foreigners should not be sac­rificed on the same public altar for the benefit of the same state.

The trader and the warrior have been fundamental antagonists throughout history. Trade does not flourish on battlefields, factories do not produce under bombard­ments, profits do not grow on rub­ble. Capitalism is a society of traders — for which it has been de­nounced by every would-be gun­man who regards trade as "self­ish" and conquest as "noble."

Let those who are actually con­cerned with peace observe that capitalism gave mankind the long­est period of peace in history — a period during which there were no wars involving the entire civ­ilised world — from the end of the Napoleonic wars in 1815 to the outbreak of World War I in 1914.

It must be remembered that the political systems of the 19th century were not pure capitalism, but mixed economies. The element of freedom, however, was dominant; it was as close to a century of capitalism as mankind has come. But the element of statism kept growing throughout the 19th cen­tury, and by the time it blasted the world in 1914, the govern­ments involved were dominated by statist policies.

Just as, in domestic affairs, all the evils caused by statism and government controls were blamed on capitalism and the free market — so, in foreign affairs, all the evils of statist policies were blamed on and ascribed to capitalism. Such myths as "capitalistic imperial­ism," "war profiteering" or the no­tion that capitalism has to win "markets" by military conquest are examples of the superficiality or the unscrupulousness of statist commentators and historians.

The essence of capitalism’s for­eign policy is free trade — i.e., the abolition of trade barriers, of pro­tective tariffs, of special privileges — the opening of the world’s trade routes to free international ex­change and competition among the private citizens of all countries dealing directly with one another. During the 19th century, it was free trade that liberated the world, undercutting and wrecking the remnants of feudalism and the statist tyranny of absolute mon­archies.

"As with Rome, the world ac­cepted the British empire because it opened world channels of energy for commerce in general. Though repressive (status) government was still imposed to a considerable degree on Ireland with very bad results, on the whole England’s invisible exports were law and free trade. Practically speaking, while England ruled the seas any man of any nation could go any­where, taking his goods and money with him, in safety." [The God of the Machine, by Isabel Paterson, Caldwell, Idaho: Caxton Printers, 1964, p. 121. Originally published by G. P. Putnam’s Sons, New York, 1943]

As in the case of Rome, when the repressive element of Eng­land’s mixed economy grew to be­come her dominant policy and turned her to statism, her empire fell apart. It was not military force that had held it together.

Capitalism wins and holds its markets by free competition, at home and abroad. A market con­quered by war can be of value (temporarily) only to those advo­cates of a mixed economy who seek to close it to international competition, impose restrictive regulations and thus acquire spe­cial privileges by force. The same type of businessmen who sought special advantages by government action in their own countries, sought special markets by govern­ment action abroad. At whose ex­pense? At the expense of the over­whelming majority of businessmen who paid the taxes for such ven­tures, but gained nothing. Who justified such policies and sold them to the public? The statist intellectuals who manufactured such doctrines as "the public in­terest" or "national prestige" or "manifest destiny."

The actual war profiteers of all mixed economies were and are of that type: men with political pull who acquire fortunes by govern­ment favor, during or after a war — fortunes which they could not have acquired on a free market.

Remember that private citizens — whether rich or poor, whether businessmen or workers — have no power to start a war. That power is the exclusive prerogative of a government. Which type of gov­ernment is more likely to plunge a country into war: a government of limited powers, bound by con­stitutional restriction — or an un­limited government, open to the pressure of any group with war­like interests or ideologies, a gov­ernment able to command armies to march at the whim of a single chief executive?

Yet it is not a limited govern­ment that today’s peace-lovers are advocating.

(Needless to say, unilateral pac­ifism is merely an invitation to aggression. Just as an individual has the right of self-defense, so has a free country if attacked. But this does not give its government the right to draft men into mili­tary service — which is the most blatantly statist violation of a man’s right to his own life. There is no contradiction between the moral and the practical: a volun­teer army is the most efficient army, as many military authori­ties have testified. A free country has never lacked volunteers when attacked by a foreign aggressor. But not many men would volun­teer for such ventures as Korea or Vietnam. Without drafted armies, the foreign policies of statist or mixed economies would not be possible.)

So long as a country is even semi-free, its mixed-economy prof­iteers are not the source of its warlike influences or policies, and are not the primary cause of its involvement in war. They are merely political scavengers cash­ing-in on a public trend. The pri­mary cause of that trend is the mixed-economy intellectuals.

Observe the link between stat­ism and militarism in the intel­lectual history of the 19th and 20th centuries. Just as the de­struction of capitalism and the rise of the totalitarian state were not caused by business or labour or any economic interests, but by the dominant statist ideology of the intellectuals — so the resurgence of the doctrine of military con­quest and armed crusades for po­litical "ideals" were the product of the same intellectuals’ belief that "the good" is to be achieved by force.

The rise of a spirit of national­istic imperialism in the United States did not come from the right, but from the left, not from big-business interests, but from the collectivist reformers who in­fluenced the policies of Theodore Roosevelt and Woodrow Wilson. For a history of these influences, see The Decline of American Lib­eralism by Arthur A. Ekirch, Jr. (New York: Longmans, Green, 1955.)

"In such instances, [writes Pro­fessor Ekirch] as the progres­sives’ increasing acceptance of compulsory military training and of the white man’s burden, there were obvious reminders of the paternalism of much of their eco­nomic reform legislation. Imperi­alism, according to a recent study of American foreign policy, was a revolt against many of the values of traditional liberalism. `The spir­it of imperialism was an exalta­tion of duty above rights, of collec­tive welfare above individual self-interest, the heroic values as op­posed to materialism, action in­stead of logic, the natural impulse rather than the pallid intellect.’ "
(p. 189. Quoted from R. E. Os­good, Ideals and Self-Interest in America’s Foreign Relations, Chi­cago: University of Chicago Press, 1953, p. 47.)
In regard to Woodrow Wilson, Professor Ekirch writes: 
"Wilson no doubt would have preferred the growth of United States foreign trade to come about as a result of free international competition, but he found it easy with his ideas of moralism and duty to rationalise direct American intervention as a means of safeguarding the na­tional interest." (p. 199.) 
And: 
"He seemed to feel that the United States had a mission to spread its institutions — which he conceived as liberal and democratic — to the more benighted areas of the world." (p. 199.) 
It was not the advocates of capitalism who helped Wilson to whip up a reluctant, peace-loving nation into the hys­teria of a military crusade—it was the "liberal" magazine The New Republic. Its editor, Herbert Croly, used such arguments as: "The American nation needs the tonic of a serious moral adven­ture."

Just as Wilson, a "liberal" re­former, led the United States in­to World War I, "to make the world safe for democracy" — so Franklin D. Roosevelt, another "liberal" reformer, led it into World War II, in the name of the "Four Freedoms." In both cases, the "conservatives" — and the big-business interests — were over­whelmingly opposed to war, but were silenced. In the case of World War II, they were smeared as "isolationists," "reactionaries" and "America-First’ers."

World War I led, not to "democ­racy," but to the creation of three dictatorships: Soviet Russia, Fascist Italy, Nazi Germany. World War II led, not to "Four Freedoms," but to the surrender of one-third of the world’s popu­lation into communist slavery.

If peace were the goal of today’s intellectuals, a failure of that magnitude — and the evidence of unspeakable suffering on so large a scale — would make them pause and check their statist premises. Instead, blind to everything but their hatred for capitalism, they are now asserting that "poverty breeds wars" (and justifying war by sympathising with a "material greed" of that kind). But the question is: what breeds poverty? If you look at the world of today and if you look back at history, you will see the answer: the de­gree of a country’s freedom is the degree of its prosperity.

Another current catch phrase is the complaint that the nations of the world are divided into the "haves" and the "have-nots." Ob­serve that the "haves" are those who have freedom, and that it is freedom that the "have-nots" have not.

If men want to oppose war, it is statism that they must oppose. So long as they hold the tribal notion that the individual is sacrificial fodder for the collective, that some men have the right to rule others by force, and that some (any) alleged "good" can justify it —there can be no peace within a na­tion and no peace among nations.

It is true that nuclear weapons have made wars too horrible to contemplate. But it makes no dif­ference to a man whether he is killed by a nuclear bomb or a dynamite bomb or an old-fash­ioned club. Nor does the number of other victims or the scale of the destruction make any difference to him. And there is something ob­scene in the attitude of those who regard horror as a matter of num­bers, who are willing to send a small group of youths to die for the tribe, but scream against the danger to the tribe itself — and more: who are willing to condone the slaughter of defenseless victims, but march in protest against wars between the well-armed.

So long as men are subjugated by force, they will fight back and use any weapons available. If a man is led to a Nazi gas chamber or a Soviet firing squad, with no voices raised to defend him, would he feel any love or concern for the survival of mankind? Or would he be more justified in feeling that a cannibalistic mankind, which tolerates dictatorships, does not deserve to survive?

If nuclear weapons are a dread­ful threat and mankind cannot afford war any longer, then man­kind cannot afford statism any longer. Let no man of good will take it upon his conscience to ad­vocate the rule of force — outside or inside his own country. Let all those who are actually concerned with peace — those who do love man and do care about his survival — realise that if war is ever to be outlawed, it is the use of force that has to be outlawed.

***

The Politics of Peace

What distinguishes man from animals is the insight into the advantages that can be derived from cooperation under the division of labour. Man curbs his innate instinct of aggression in order to cooperate with other human beings. The more he wants to improve his material well-being, the more he must expand the system of the division of labour. Concomitantly he must more and more restrict the sphere in which he resorts to military action. The emergence of the international division of labour requires the total abolition of war. Such is the essence of the laissez-faire philosophy of Manchester.

This philosophy is, of course, incompatible with statolatry. In its context the state, the social apparatus of violent oppression, is entrusted with the protection of the smooth operation of the market economy against the onslaughts of antisocial individuals and gangs. Its function is indispensable and beneficial, but it is an ancillary function only. There is no reason to idolise the police power and ascribe to it omnipotence and omniscience. There are things which it can certainly not accomplish. It cannot conjure away the scarcity of the factors of production, it cannot make people more prosperous, it cannot raise the productivity of labour. All it can achieve is to prevent gangsters from frus­trating the efforts of those people who are intent upon promoting material well-being.

~ LUDWIG VON MISES, from his magnum opus Human Action


Ayn Rand

Ayn Rand

**Ayn Rand (1905–1982) was a Russian-American novelist, philosopher, playwright, and screenwriter. She is known for her two best-selling novels, The Fountainhead and Atlas Shrugged, and for developing a philosophical system she called Objectivism. She corresponded with FEE's founder Leonard Read and provided a meaningful intellectual influence over free-market thought in the second half of the twentieth century. Her influence continues to expand through her fiction and nonfiction works and the educational work being done on Objectivism. 

This reprinted article was originally published on FEE.org. Read the original article. And watch this 2021 analysis of Rand's article ...







No comments: